Schultz - A system of Axioms for Hyperbolic Geometry.pdf

(327 KB) Pobierz
X:\JG-2008\JG-8-1903\JG-8-1903.dvi
2008 Birkhauser Verlag Basel/Switzerland
0047-2468/010185-8, published online 21 November 2008
DOI 10.1007/s00022-008-1903-9
Journal of Geometry
A System of Axioms for Hyperbolic Geometry
John W. Schutz
This paper is dedicated to my parents,
Edith Schutz ( nee Edit Kertesz, 9 / 09 / 1917 Budapest – 4 / 07 / 2005) and
Steven Joseph Schutz ( Istvan Jozsef Schutz, b. 12 / 05 / 1912 , Budapest )
Abstract. Three–dimensional hyperbolic geometry is characterized using ax-
ioms of order, incidence, dimension, continuity and, instead of an axiom of
parallels, there is an axiom of “rigidity” and, rather than several axioms of
congruence, there is one axiom of symmetry. It is claimed that this system of
axioms is simpler than the system of independent axioms of Moore [15].
Mathematics Subject Classification (2000). 50A10, 51M10.
Keywords. Axioms, hyperbolic geometry.
1. Introduction
Hyperbolic geometry will be developed from an axiomatic system which can be
shown to specify the interior of an ellipsoid with the projective cross–ratio as an
invariant metric.
Projective geometry was axiomatised by von Staudt [25,26] and described in terms
of homogeneous coordinates by Plucker [17,18]. Cayley [6] showed that the projec-
tive cross–ratio could be used as a projectively invariant measure of distance and
then Klein [13] developed the first model of hyperbolic geometry which consisted
of the interior of an ellipse in which line segments are equipped with the pro-
jective cross-ratio as an invariant measure of distance. The development of these
ideas is described in considerable detail by Torretti [27] and these and subsequent
developments in non–Euclidean geometry are described by Karzel and Kroll [12]
and reviewed by Karzel [11]. A complete description of hyperbolic geometry and
projective metrics in terms of homogeneous coordinates is given by Busemann and
Kelly [5].
J. geom. 90 (2008), 185–192
c
642395399.001.png
186
J. W. Schutz
J. Geom.
Klein [14] first expounded the idea that projective geometry could be developed
as an embedding space for a a geometry of “points” and “lines” with a relation of
“intermediacy”. Veblen [28] used this approach to specify Euclidean and hyperbolic
geometry with an axiomatic system whose twelve axioms allow the given geometry
to be embedded in a three–dimensional projective space over the reals with a metric
defined by the choice of a polarity on the “plane at infinity”.
In the present axiomatic system we consider undefined sets of “points” and “lines”
with a relation of “intermediacy” which satisfy the first eleven (of twelve) axioms
of Veblen, together with one additional relation of “congruence” and two further
axioms of “isotropy” and “rigidity”. The first eleven axioms correspond to those
of Veblen and imply that the geometry may be considered as a convex region of
projective space. The axiom of “isotropy” then restricts the region to be either
an ane subspace or the interior of an ellipsoid, by a theorem of Aleksandrov [1],
Busemann [4] and Schutz [24]. Finally the axiom of “rigidity” excludes the ane
subspace and the only remaining possibility is the Klein model of hyperbolic ge-
ometry in which the metric is defined by the “motions” or automorphisms of the
space.
Even though the the cited results of Aleksandrov and Busemann use deep results
from transformation group theory, the result of Schutz uses standard results of
Euclidean, ane and projective geometry. Consequently hyperbolic geometry can
be developed axiomatically using elementary techniques.
2. The system of axioms
The name “ordered geometry” has been used by Coxeter [7] to describe the “ge-
ometry of serial order” which can be developed in terms of a single undefined
ternary relation of order called “betweenness” or “intermediacy”. This geometry
can be developed without any mention of congruence and without any axiom of
uniqueness of parallelism. The discussion of Coxeter is based on that of Veblen [28]
but is more detailed and provides detailed proofs with references to acknowledge
the many sources [2, 3, 8, 9, 16, 21–23, 29]. Veblen actually states a total of twelve
axioms but the twelfth axiom is not required for “ordered geometry”.
The geometry resulting from Veblen’s [28] Axioms I to XI is the geometry of
incidence and order of a three–dimensional convex open domain. It will be shown
in Lemma 1 that this geometry can be embedded as a convex open domain in a
three–dimensional projective space over the reals. Any other equivalent system of
axioms, such as the axiomatic system of Coxeter [7], could also be used. Veblen
claims and establishes the mutual independence of the first twelve axioms and, in a
subsequent article, Moore [15] also uses a modified system of mutually independent
axioms.
Vol. 90 (2008)
A System of Axioms for Hyperbolic Geometry
187
2.1. Undefined basis
Hyperbolic geometry is
= P
, [ ... ]
H
,
L
where
P
is a set whose elements are called points ,
L
is a set of subsets of
P
called
lines and [ ... ] is a ternary relation on the set of points of
P
called a betweenness
relation .
2.2. Axioms of incidence and order
Axiom 1. There exist at least two distinct points.
Axiom 2. If points A, B, C are in the order [ ABC ] , they are in the order [ CBA ].
Axiom 3. If points A, B, C are in the order [ ABC ] , they are not in the order
[ BCA ].
Axiom 4. If points A, B, C are in the order [ ABC ], then A is distinct from C .
Axiom 5. If A and B are any two distinct points, there exists a point C such that
A, B, C are in the order [ ABC ] .
For distinct points A, B ,the line
AB :=
{
A, B
}∪ X :[ ABX ] , [ AXB ] , [ XAB ] ,X
∈P .
The points X in the order [ AXB ] constitute the segment
|
AB
|
where A and B are
the end-points of the segment. The ray
|
AB
:=
{
A, B
}∪|
AB
|∪{
X :[ ABX ]: X
∈P}
is the set of all points on the half–line from A in the direction of B .
Axiom 6. If points C and D ( C
= D ) lie on the line AB , then A lies on the line
CD .
Axiom 7. If there exist three distinct points, there exist three points A , B , C not
in any of the orders [ ABC ] , [ BCA ], or [ CAB ].
Three distinct points not lying on the same line are the vertices of a triangle ABC,
whose sides are the segments
|
AB
|
,
BC
|
,
|
CA
|
, and whose boundary consists of its
vertices and the points of its sides.
Axiom 8. If three distinct points A, B ,and C do not lie on the same line, and D
and E are two points in the orders [ BCD ] and [ CEA ], then a point F exists in
the order [ AF B ] and such that D, E, F lie on the same line.
A point O is in the interior of a triangle if it lies on a segment, the end-points of
which are points of different sides of the triangle. The set of such points O is the
interior of the triangle.
If A, B, C form a triangle, the plane ABC consists of all points collinear with any
two points of the sides of the triangle.
|
188
J. W. Schutz
J. Geom.
Axiom 9. If there exist three points not lying in the same line, there exists a plane
ABC such that there is a point D not lying in the plane ABC .
. The points of
faces, edges, and vertices constitute the surface of the tetrahedron.
If A, B, C, D are the vertices of a tetrahedron, the space ABCD consists of all
points collinear with any two points of the faces of the tetrahedron.
Axiom 10. If there exist four points neither lying in the same line nor lying in the
same plane, there exists a space ABCD such that there is no point E not collinear
with two points of the space, ABCD .
|
AB
|
|
BC
|
,
|
CD
|
|
DA
|
|
AC
|
,
|
BD
|
The next axiom resembles the second–order geometric axiom of the same name in
the axiom systems of Hilbert [10], Veblen [28] and Moore [15].
For a given line L , a sequence of points A 0 ,A 1 ,A 2 ,...
B
=
{
B b :
A i
= A 0 , [ A 0 A i B b ]; B b
L
}
is called
the set of bounds of the sequence :if
B
is non–empty we say that the sequence is
bounded and, if there is a bound B c ∈B
such that [ A 0 B c B b ] (for all B b ∈B\{
B c }
)
we say that B c is a closest bound.
Axiom 11 (Continuity). Any bounded linearly–ordered sequence of points has a
closest bound.
These first eleven axioms imply that the set of points is an open convex three–
dimensional) subset (of an ane subspace) of three–dimensional projective space
P
Lemma 1 (Convex subset). The set of points
P
is a convex open subset of some
a ne subset of
P
3 .
Proof. We first consider the special case of a a plane subspace Π of
H
. A line
through a point A
∈P
meets the boundary
P
in a point B (where the prime in-
satisfies the order
properties implied by Axioms 1–11 (which are used by Coxeter [7] to establish an
“ordered” or “descriptive” geometry) so the line AB separates the remaining set of
points of
P
). The set of points
P
Π into two components or “sides”. Each other line (of Π) through B
intersects at most one of these “sides” and the two “sides” specify disconnected
subsets of lines (through B ). These subsets meet the projective extension of any
other line through A in open (disconnected) segments. If the point A is excluded
from this projective line, the continuity property applies to the remaining linearly
ordered subset, so there is at least one point between the two open segments.
Therefore, through the point B , there is some line l which does not meet
P∩
P
.
If A, B, C ,and D are four points not lying in the same plane, they form a tetrahe-
dron ABCD whose faces are the interiors of the triangles ABC, BCD, CDA, DAB
(if the triangles exist) whose vertices are the four points, A, B, C, and D ,and
whose edges are the segments
,
,
,
L with the order property
[ A i A i +1 A i +2 ] (for all i ) is called a linearly–ordered sequence and will be denoted
as [ A 0 A 1 A 2 ... ]. The set
3 as we will now show.
dicates that the point does not belong to
Vol. 90 (2008)
A System of Axioms for Hyperbolic Geometry
189
To extend the proof to three–dimensions, we consider the set of planes which
contain the line l . As in the two–dimensional case, the plane Π separates the
remaining set of points of
P
and which
, form two disconnected components. Through A take any line which is
not contained in Π: the two disconnected components meet the projective extension
of this line in open (disconnected) segments and, as in the previous case, there is
now some plane (containing l ) which belongs to neither component and therefore
contains no points of
P
P
.
2.3. The axiom of symmetry
Axiom 12 (Isotropy). There is a point A such that, for each pair of distinct rays
|
and
|
AC
, there is an automorphism of
H
=
P
,
L
, [ ... ]
which maps
|
AB
onto
|
AC
.
This axiom ensures that the convex domain is either a three–dimensional ane
space or the interior of an ellipsoid, as follows from characterisations of ellipsoids
by Aleksandrov [1], Busemann [4] and Schutz [24] which may be stated as:
Theorem 2 (Projective isotropy theorem). Let
V
be a convex open subset of some
a ne subset of
P
3 .If
V
is isotropic with respect to some point A
∈V
, then
V
is
either an ellipsoid or an a ne subspace of
P
3 .
2.4. The axiom of rigidity
The next axiom is related to a concept of congruence which is based on the idea
that equality of segments may be demonstrated by the motion of a “rigid ruler”.
This concept is either imposed upon the geometry or, if a ruler is regarded as
existing within a space, the “rigidity” is related to the possible motions of the
space and, accordingly, the concept of congruence is defined by the automorphisms
of
H
=
P
,
L
, [ ... ]
which maps a segment
|
AB
|
onto
another segment
|
CD
, we say that the segments
|
AB
|
and
|
CD
|
are congruent and
| =
. The axiom of rigidity will be stated for a single segment.
Axiom 13 (Rigidity). There are two distinct points A, B such that the segment
|
|
AB
|
CD
|
AB
|
is not congruent to a subsegment of itself.
which are projectivities of the embedding three–dimensional
projective space. An ane subspace of a projective space has automorphisms of
any segment onto any other segment: the axiom of rigidity therefore excludes the
possibility of an ane space, which leaves the interior of an ellipsoid as the only
possible subset of points corresponding to
P
,
L
, [ ... ]
. The definition of congruence im-
plies that the concept of length of segments must be defined by the projectively
invariant cross–ratio.
P
into two disconnected subsets or “sides”: if we exclude
the plane Π, the remaining subset of planes which contain the line l
intersect
AB
.
If there is an automorphism of
H
|
we write
The concept of congruence is based upon the existence of automorphisms of
H
=
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin