Prostitution.pdf

(109 KB) Pobierz
343
F
The ‘subject’ of prostitution
Interpreting the discursive, symbolic and material
position of sex/work in feminist theory
Feminist Theory
Copyright © 2004
SAGE Publications
(London,
Thousand Oaks, CA
and New Delhi)
vol. 5(3): 343–355.
1464–7001
DOI: 10.1177/1464700104046983
Jane Scoular Strathclyde University
Prostitution is often viewed in feminist theory as the sine qua non of the
female condition under patriarchy. Frequently cited as ‘the absolute
embodiment of patriarchal male privilege’ (Kesler, 2002: 19), the highly
gendered nature of commercial sex appears to offer a graphic example of
male domination, exercised through the medium of sexuality.
This construction is, however, as convincing as it is problematic. By
reviewing the work of Shelia Jeffries, Judith Walkowitz, Gail Pheterson,
Shannon Bell, Jo Doezema, Kamala Kempadoo and Jo Phoenix, I aim to
illustrate that feminist writers, by assuming different theoretical lenses,
offer diverse interpretations of the subject of prostitution – both in terms
of women’s subjective positions and as a problem of a particular type.
Prostitution therefore rather than having a singular meaning is more
usefully viewed as an important crucible for testing the central mainstays
of feminist theory. As Donna Guy notes:
Full of apparent contradictions and discrepancies, the history of modern prosti-
tution control offers a dynamic perspective on the private lives of women as well
as the public functioning of medicine, patriarchy and the nation state and
emphasizes the need to understand how gender and sexuality are interrelated
inextricably to race, cultural diversity and economic circumstances. (Guy, 1995:
182)
As this quotation suggests, and as I will demonstrate in the course of this
article, there are limitations in viewing prostitution as straightforwardly
paradigmatic, given the contingencies and diversity of the structures under
which its materializes.
keywords identity, post-modernism, prostitution, sex work, violence
The very idea of prostitution – radical feminist perspectives
Prostitution remains morally undesirable . . . because it is one of those most
graphic examples of men’s domination over women. (Pateman, 1983: 56)
854329846.011.png 854329846.012.png
 
854329846.013.png 854329846.001.png 854329846.002.png
 
344
Feminist Theory 5(3)
The prostitute symbolizes the value of women in society. She is paradigmatic of
women’s social, sexual and economic subordination, in that her status is the
basic unit by which all women’s value is measured and to which all women can
be reduced. (Giobbe, 1990: 77)
Radical feminist insights into prostitution have done most to highlight the
harms experienced by women in this area and have illustrated the inequal-
ities in prostitution within the context of a gendered analysis of the state
and sexuality. The defining characteristic of work in this area, expressed
in the writings of Kate Millet (1975), Kathleen Barry (1979, 1995), Carole
Pateman (1983, 1988), Catherine MacKinnon (1987, 1989) and Andrea
Dworkin (1987, 1989), is an understanding of prostitution as violence
against women – violence not only in the practice of prostitution but more
fundamentally in the very idea of ‘buying sex’ which is considered so inex-
tricably linked to a system of heterosexuality and male power that it
represents ‘the absolute embodiment of patriarchal male privilege’ (Kesler,
2002: 19). 1
Shelia Jeffries’ work The Idea of Prostitution (1997) is a useful reference
point as it aims to defend this ideological position which, she states, since
the late 1960s has ‘analysed prostitution uncompromisingly as the ultimate
in the reduction of women to sexual objects which can be bought and sold,
to a sexual slavery that lies at the root of marriage and prostitution and
forms the foundation of women’s oppression’ (Jeffries, 1997: 2). The notion
of sexual slavery, first coined by Barry, is one that Jeffries maintains
throughout this book as she seeks to counter critiques that focus on prosti-
tution as women’s deviant sexuality:
[Prostitution is] male sexual behaviour characterised by three elements variously
combined: barter, promiscuity, and emotional indifference. Any man is a prosti-
tution abuser who, for the purposes of his sexual satisfaction, habitually or inter-
mittently reduces another human being into a sexual object by the use of money
or other mercenary considerations. (Jeffries, 1997: 4)
An understanding of prostitution as a practice that contributes to women’s
oppression, and as a foundational idea that pre-determines it, informs the
contemporary campaigns by radical feminists in the political and legal
arenas to establish all prostitution as a violation of women’s human rights,
thus ‘exploding the false distinction between forced and voluntary prosti-
tution’ (Jeffries, 1997: 10). Through the Coalition Against Trafficking in
Women (CATW), Jeffries and other prominent radical feminists focus atten-
tion on trafficking as the sexual slavery of women and children and seek
to challenge its ‘widespread support’. 2 This ‘support’ is considered to
emanate from an apparent array of actors (sex liberals, queer theorists,
pimps, sex tourists and postmodernists) who consider alternative influ-
ences or frameworks such as work, choice and sex. Jeffries cites this diverse
group as ‘united in their resistance to a feminist politics of prostitution’,
preferring to ‘sustain women’s exploitation’ in this field (Jeffries, 1997: 6).
The importance of this work, which has provided a vital space to articu-
late the harms women have experienced and continue to experience
‘under’ eroticized power relations, can be overshadowed in the critiques
854329846.003.png
 
854329846.004.png
Scoular: The ‘subject’ of prostitution
345
that emerge from alternative voices in the sex industry and from post-
modernists. An uncompromised account of domination does offer oppor-
tunities for action in the face of the seeming nihilism of more abstract
postmodern theories and the de-politicization created by the normalization
of heterosexual power differentials and the apparent market inevitability
of their commodification.
Nevertheless, the move from empirical, and at times partial, accounts of
women’s experiences in prostitution to an ideological position is
frequently achieved at the expense of a recognition of women’s agency and
the complexities and contradictions inherent in analysing selling sex
across space and time, without regard for the structuring roles of culture,
class and race.
The alienated subject of prostitution
The importance of gender in structuring the sale of sex informs a radical
perspective on prostitution. Rather than representing freedom or diversity,
the practice of women selling sex is considered the epitome of the oppres-
sive sexual relations, ‘the public recognition of men’s mastery’ (Mac-
Kinnon, 1993: 13). Sexuality is considered as the primary dynamic in the
ordering of society, represented in MacKinnon’s maxim: ‘Sexuality is to
feminism, what work is to Marxism; that which is most one’s own and yet
that which is most taken away’ (MacKinnon, 1982: 515). Carole Pateman,
in The Sexual Contract , engenders the political fiction of the social contact
to demonstrate the centrality of sexual possession to male–female relations
in European societies and the role of prostitution in maintaining this
dynamic: ‘womanhood . . . is confirmed in sexual activity, and when a
prostitute contracts out the use of her body she is thus selling herself in a
very real way’ (Pateman, 1988: 207, emphasis in original).
There are, however, a number of problems with such accounts. By over-
determining gendered power-dynamics critics have noted that domination
theory simply essentializes and fails to move outside the phallocentric
imaginary (Cornell, 1995; Brown, 1995; Scoular, 1996). 3 This is evident in
the quotation above where, in one rhetorical swoop, all women are reduced
to prostitutes and prostitutes to their sex acts. Not only does this reify an
image of the prostitute as sexual subordinate, it also sustains the myths and
norms of the sex industry, of potent men and submissive women, rather
than transforming them (Shrage, 1994: 134). Gender and sexuality clearly
play important structuring roles in prostitution but it is a phenomenon that
cannot be reduced to either gender or sexuality (Zatz, 1997: 279). 4 In doing
so radical feminist theories reduce women’s identity to a single trait,
regardless of the structuring roles of money, culture or race. In identifying
sex more than other bodily mediated activities, such as childcare, nursing
or domestic activities, radical feminists ascribe a particular value to sex,
which is then used to argue against its commodification (Oerton and
Phoenix, 2001: 387). Pateman, for example, defines the difference between
paid sex and loving sex as: ‘[the] difference between the reciprocal expres-
sion of desire and unilateral subjection to sexual acts with the consolation
854329846.005.png
 
854329846.006.png
346
Feminist Theory 5(3)
of payment: it is the difference for women between freedom and subjec-
tion’ (Pateman, 1988: 204). Barry echoes this when she notes that ‘when
sex is not explicitly treated as genuine human interaction, it dehumanises
the experience and thereby dominates women’ (Barry, 1995: 28).
Not only does this confirm current normative understandings of
‘genuine’ sex as in some way outside power, it also, as Zatz observes,
accepts the culturally specific processes that separate work from relation-
ships of intimacy. The economic dimension is important in this context.
Although seen by radical feminists as just an exacerbating variable, in an
always-dominant sexual hierarchy, the presence of money has important
structural consequences. 5 Feminists have highlighted the public/private
norms of instrumental rationality and love that operate to obscure the role
of desire in the market and to place burdens on groups, especially women,
whose labour in an affective private world goes unrecognized (Zatz, 1997:
303; Olsen, 1983: 1497). Prostitution, however, challenges this dualism.
Zatz (1997: 303) describes it as a ‘bifurcated event’ – an act that cannot be
identified as singularly a market transaction or the realization of private
desire. The confusion this creates fuels the whore stigma, which as Mc-
Clintock (1992: 73) observes, reflects deeply felt anxieties about women
trespassing the dangerous boundaries between private and public. It is also
met with criminalization which attempts to force back public elements of
prostitution into the realm of private sexuality, thus keeping the economy
and sexuality symbolically separated: ‘By denying prostitution the status
of work criminalization helps patrol the boundary between the sex/affec-
tive labour routinely assigned to and expected of women and practices
deserving of the financial and status rewards of “work” ’ (Zatz, 1997: 287).
Failure to recognize the role of stigma and law in structuring the marginal
status of sex work means, as Zatz perceptively notes, that radical feminists
often underestimate how much of what they identify as harmful in prostitution
is a product, not of the inherent character of sex work or sexuality but rather of
the specific regimes of criminalization and denigration that serve to marginalize
and oppress sex workers while constraining and distorting sex work’s radical
potential. (Zatz, 1997: 289)
Sex radicals
The most obvious critique that emerges in response to domination theory
is from those whose experience lies beyond a myopic interpretation of
complex social practices. As Doezema notes, ‘In claiming the “injured
prostitute” as the ontological and epistemological basis of feminist truth
[radical feminist work] forecloses the possibility of political confrontation
with sex workers who claim a different experience’ (Doezema, 2001: 28).
This tension, is vividly captured in Gail Pheterson’s accounts of the first
Congress of Whores (in 1989) where, describing themselves as ‘feminists
in exile’ 6 (Pheterson, 1989: 17), prostitutes organized not only to campaign
against legal discrimination but also to resist accounts which cast them as
mere victims. Pheterson highlights the beginnings of counter movements
of ‘sex workers’ in the West which formed directly in response to legal
854329846.007.png
 
854329846.008.png
Scoular: The ‘subject’ of prostitution
347
discrimination but also in response to feminist hesitations around viewing
prostitution as work (Bell, 1987; Delacoste and Alexander, 1988).
In A Vindication of the Rights of Whores , Pheterson (1989) subverts
Wollstonecraft’s early liberal feminist manifesto to ground an ongoing
campaign for the civil rights of women in the sex industry. Seemingly
flippant at times, for example, the demand for the right ‘to charge for what
other women give for free’ (Delacoste and Alexander, 1988: 273), sex
worker narratives do offer important counter-hegemonic insights: ‘its open
challenge both to the identification of sex acts with acts of desire and to
the opposition between erotic/affective activity and economic life’ (Zatz,
1997: 277).
Alongside postmodern work that has theoretically refined and bolstered
sex worker discourse, support has been garnered from those who similarly
oppose dominant notions of appropriate sexual behaviour and campaign
against the legal constraints on their apparent ‘deviant’ identities. While
this alliance is understandable given the lack of unconditional support
from large parts of the feminist movement and the shared experience of
engaging in sexual activity outside the legitimated boundaries of married,
heterosexual monogamy, assimilating sex work with ‘deviant’ sexualities
is, at times, problematic.
As diverse as the work in the area of sexuality is, there is a tendency
amongst the most rhetorical writers to cast the deviant category itself as
normative, especially when striving for legal recognition, at the expense of
more pluralistic struggles around sexuality (Bower, 1994; Herman and
Stychin, 1995; Stychin and Herman, 2000). Sex worker discourses, at
times, fall into this mode of thinking. Pheterson, for example, maintains
that law ‘contributes to the stigmatization and suppression of all active and
autonomous expressions of female desire’ (Pheterson, 1989: 23, 194;
Shrage, 1994: 134). By equating the restrictions on women’s sexual activity
with the suppression of an apparent ‘natural’ sexual drive she inadver-
tently reinforces dominant notions of sex as pre-social and confirms the
centrality of sexuality to subjects’ identity. Such an approach ignores the
role of law and material structures in producing, as well as constraining,
sexual preferences and acts (Foucault, 1978).
By moving beyond this, identity politics, whether for gay rights or for
sex workers’ rights, risks affirming a ‘fully constituted and bounded’
identity which is in fact ‘created’ by the power structures it aims to
critique. As Minow notes,
Just as conventional notions of objectivity failed to recognize the authority of the
voices of the relatively powerless, alternative notions of authority in subjective
accounts are defective in their inattention to material, historical experiences
beyond individual subjectivity. (Minow, 1993: 1437)
By contrast, work in sexuality which recognizes the historical and cultural
contingency of dominant forms of sexuality (Foucault, 1978; Rubin, 1984;
Weeks, 1985; Bell, 1994) helps develop a less normative approach which
casts prostitute rights not as ‘another configuration of sexual desire and
pleasure’ but as a strategic movement that attempts to resist the structuring
854329846.009.png
 
854329846.010.png
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin