S. Johansson, Origins of language (rozdział 10).pdf

(192 KB) Pobierz
Origins of Language
Origins of Language
Constraints on hypotheses
Sverker Johansson
University of Jönköping
John Benjamins Publishing Company
Amsterdam
Philadelphia
/
73593309.001.png
TM
The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements
of American National Standard for Information Sciences – Permanence
of Paper for Printed Library Materials, ansi z39.48-1984.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Sverker Johansson
Origins of Language : Constraints on hypotheses / Sverker Johansson.
p. cm. (Converging Evidence in Language and Communication
Research, issn 1566–7774 ; v. 5)
Includes bibliographical references and index.
1. Language and languages--Origin. 2. Human evolution. 3.
Biolinguistics.
P116.O76
2005
401--dc22
2004066031
isbn 90 272 3891 X (Eur.) / 1 58811 629 8 (US) (Hb; alk. paper)
© 2005 – John Benjamins B.V.
No part of this book may be reproduced in any form, by print, photoprint, microfilm, or
any other means, without written permission from the publisher.
John Benjamins Publishing Co. · P.O. Box 36224 · 1020 me Amsterdam · The Netherlands
John Benjamins North America · P.O. Box 27519 · Philadelphia pa 19118-0519 · usa
73593309.002.png
C HAPTER 10
WHY DID LANGUAGE EVOLVE?
In order to understand the evolution of language, we must advance our under-
standing of the purpose of language, and ‘purpose’ in an evolutionary context is
synonymous with selective advantage (Ganger & Stromswold, 1998). Different
hypotheses concerning the original selective advantage that drove the evolution of
language will be discussed in this chapter.
Evolution of complex and specialized features does not occur without being
driven by some selective pressure — some evolutionary advantage accruing to
those who possess the feature. As discussed in Section 9.3, it is well established
that language is such a complex and specialized feature (Pinker & Bloom, 1990).
But what was the crucial advantage conferred by language, that drove its evolu-
tion? One may think that the advantages of having a language are obvious — as
Lieberman (2003a) points out “it is difficult to identify any aspect of human be-
havior (...) that would not profit from [...] language, ...” (p. 670) — but that would
instead raise the question of why only humans have acquired it, why not a lot of
other animals as well, if it is so useful?
Szathmary (2001) identifies two possible explanations for the uniqueness of an
apparently useful feature, such as language:
1. Variation-limited: The requisite combination of mutations has a very low prob-
ability of occurring.
2. Selection-limited: The feature will bring a selective advantage only under very
rare circumstances.
The first possibility is in principle conceivable in the case of language, but it would
mean that the appearance of language in the human lineage, rather than that of
chimps or cockroaches, is a matter of pure chance. In that case, the problem of
language origins is not amenable to analysis, and not very interesting in any case
(though Szathmary (2001) calls the possibility ‘amusing’). The miraculous salta-
tionist models of language origins formerly favored by e.g., Chomsky (1988) and
Bickerton (1990), discussed in Section 9.5, belong in this category.
The second possibility is more interesting, and does appear more plausible, as
humans have many other unusual features, that may provide the unique circum-
194 Origins of language
stances that would favor language emergence. In that case, the problem at hand
is to identify whatever it was in human history, that made language particularly
advantageous for our ancestors, but not for the other apes. This has close parallels
with hypotheses concerning why our brains are so much larger, discussed in Sec-
tion 5.3.1. The different levels of evolution, as well as the features and limitations
of evolutionary processes, reviewed in Chapter 3, should also be kept in mind.
A particularly common pitfall here is the teleological scenario — that our an-
cestors evolved language because they needed it for some purpose or other. Future
utility of a trait is never valid as an explanation for its evolution, as this entails
backwards causation. Tenable hypotheses must be structured around selection
scenarios, instead — why did people with incipient stages of language have a
reproductive advantage over people without?
The issues raised in Section 6.3 must also be considered — the selective ad-
vantage of language must actually benefit the spread of the speaker’s genes, not
just the general welfare of the group. Hypotheses of language evolution cannot be
based exclusively on how information recipients benefit from language, without
explaining how that benefit spreads back to the speaker.
Another important aspect, related to the previous points, is the context in which
language evolved. Before the advent of agriculture (which certainly postdates lan-
guage), humans lived as hunter-gatherers, in modest-sized tribes, presumably with
a lifestyle and social structure not vastly different from that of the few remaining
present-day hunter-gatherers. The chimpanzee lifestyle can reasonably be called
hunter-gatherer as well, though it is quite different from that of human hunter-
gatherers. Thus it appears not unreasonable to assume that language evolved in
a hunter-gatherer context, in tribes with a social structure somewhere in between
that of chimps and modern hunter-gatherers. This would be the ‘Environment of
Evolutionary Adaptedness’ (EEA), the Stone Age environment for which evolu-
tion has shaped us — the time since we abandoned the hunter-gatherer lifestyle is
much too short for any substantial evolutionary changes (Daly & Wilson, 1999;
Nesse & Williams, 1994; Byrne, 2000, but see also Irons (1998)). Reasonable hy-
potheses of language evolution must postulate that language carried some crucial
advantage for people in such an EEA society — advantages that language confers
only in modern industrialized (or even farming) societies are irrelevant.
Numerous hypotheses have been proposed as answers to these questions about
human language evolution, a selection of which will be evaluated here. In order
to provide some structure and overview, the hypotheses will be classified under
several categories, though the boundaries between the categories are sometimes
fluid.
Why did language evolve? 195
10.1 Hunting
An obvious starting point is to postulate that language evolved for the purpose of
communication, and that the main selective advantage gained by improved com-
munication was enhanced coordination of group activities. Prominent among the
group activities discussed in this context is hunting, which has played a central
role in many scenarios for human evolution (Landau, 1991; Sagan, 1977), but
more general resource acquisition activities can be included here as well (Cziko,
1995). Apart from communication during hunts, the hunting argument has also
been connected with the teaching argument of Section 10.4 below:
The ‘quality education’ needed to become an expert Pleistocene hunter could not
do without a complex form of information transmittal interaction in which the tran-
scendence of the here and now, [...] played a key role. (Roebroeks, 2001, p. 451,
emphasis in original).
Hunting-related communication could be a significant force in our evolution, only
if hunting was actually of major importance for our subsistence. Contrary to this,
it is commonly asserted that most hunter-gatherers, at least in the tropical areas
relevant to early human evolution (Ragir, 2000), don’t get nearly as much food
from hunting as from gathering. Kaplan et al. (2000), however, contest this claim,
and review a number of studies of actual calories hunted and gathered by members
of various tribes — on average, an adult hunter produces twice as many calories
per day as an adult gatherer. Kaplan et al. (2000) furthermore trace the ‘common
knowledge’ that hunting is unimportant back to a single study of questionable
generality (Lee, 1979, cited in Kaplan et al. (2000)).
The Inuit, who live in an Arctic environment with little plant food to gather,
incontrovertibly get most of their food from hunting, and very likely so did the
Neanderthals of Ice Age Europe, for similar reasons. Isotopic evidence from Ne-
anderthal fossils indicates that meat from large herbivores was a major part of their
diet, which implies that hunting was an economically vital activity (Richards et al.,
2000; Bocherens et al., 2001). But living in a glacial environment is a very late
development in human history, well after H sapiens and Neanderthals had gone
their separate ways, so an Arctic origin of language does not appear plausible.
Nevertheless, with the evidence presented by Kaplan et al. (2000) it would ap-
pear that hunting is highly significant for modern human hunter-gatherers, and by
implication has been important for at least the later part of our evolution, so that a
role for hunting in the evolution of language is not excluded on these grounds.
There are, however, a few problems with the notion that hunter coordination
was a major driving force in language evolution. To begin with, modern humans
do not use all that much language during a hunt — it is a rather silent activity
(Dunbar, 2003b).
Furthermore non-human social carnivores manage to coordinate their collabo-
rative hunts without using language (Brinck & Gardenfors, 2003). This of course
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin