THEORY AND PRACTICE OF ANATTA.pdf

(94 KB) Pobierz
660478567 UNPDF
BECOMING AND UN-BECOMING: THE
THEORY AND PRACTICE OF ANATTA
Clare Carlisle
Theory
Who am I?
The doctrine of anatta, selflessness, is at the heart of the Buddha’s teaching,
and it ties together metaphysical, ethical, meditative, and devotional facets of
Buddhism. Like many spiritual and philosophical traditions, Buddhism rests on the
idea that wisdom is liberating, but unlike most other traditions teaches that the
wisdom that must be sought is not about oneself, but about one’s selflessness.
Western philosophers, habituated to Christian, Platonic, and Cartesian ways of
thinking, and to a substantialist, unrepentantly self-centred grammar, may find
anatta difficult to understand, to accept, to imagine.
Actually, anatta is so simple that it can hardly be called a doctrine: it is a
denial, a denial that ‘I’ really exist. The Buddhist philosopher’s challenge is not to
argue or to prove that there is no such thing as a distinct, enduring self—in any
case, the truth of anatta only becomes meaningful (i.e. liberating) in practice,
when it is experienced—but to account for the phenomenon of selfhood. What is
this ‘I’ who, it seems, experiences and remembers things; worries, loves, hopes,
suffers, grows old; seeks wisdom; practices Buddhism, and so on? The
phenomenon of self-identity is not only, or even primarily, an outcome of
introspection: if we deny the reality of the self, we need to explain how it is that we
are able to know and understand another person; to recognise an old
acquaintance, even from a distance, after many years of absence. How does a
Buddhist philosopher account for the continuity, consistency, and stability of a
human being through time, without recourse to concepts such as substance and
essence?
For some time now I have been developing an account of selfhood that is
based on the concept of habit. For reasons that will soon become clear, this focus
on habit is very useful, and rather well suited, to the European Buddhist
philosopher I find myself to be. Many thinkers in our western tradition have
emphasised the role of habit in human life: for example, Aristotle and Aquinas
regard habit as a second nature, which develops through actions and shapes
Contemporary Buddhism, Vol. 7, No. 1, May 2006
ISSN 1463-9947 print/1476-7953 online/06/010075-89
q 2006 Taylor & Francis DOI: 10.1080/14639940600878034
660478567.001.png
76 C. CARLISLE
a person’s moral character; Hume argues that ‘habit or custom’ is ‘the great guide
of human life’ (1975, 44), 1 the source of our beliefs and judgements about
causation, the external world, and personal identity. William James and Marcel
Proust both go further in seeing habit as a fundamental principle of the human
person as a whole. More recently, a few philosophers have gone so far as to
identify the self with habit: Gilles Deleuze suggests that ‘we are habits, nothing but
habits’ (1991, x); Merleau-Ponty describes the embodied self—‘the lived body’ or
‘my own body’—as ‘my basic habit’ (1962, 91). John Dewey writes that ‘all habits
... constitute the self’ (1922, 25), and Krishnamurti claims that ‘I am my habit, my
habit is me ... my whole life is a structure of habits’ (1986, 125–7). In an earlier
essay on habit, I tried to argue for and develop this idea that habit can account for
selfhood (see Carlisle 2006). I no longer wish to make this claim, not least because
it rests on an assumption that we know what the self is, what its boundaries are,
and are therefore able to reflect on the extent to which habit can account for it.
But how would we know when we have fully accounted for a self that remains
undetermined?
Nevertheless, in taking seriously the suggestion that ‘we are habits, nothing
but habits’, I made some progress in thinking through the conceptual structure of
habit, its mode of operation, its transcendental conditions, its connections to
personal identity, and its ethical relevance; and I think that this does tell us more
about the self—in a way that accommodates the theory and the practice of
anatta. Now, by identifying the self with habit I am merely suggesting that we
work with a certain definition of the self, delimited by habit. In other words, we
draw from the concept of habit a provisional determination of the self. Whatever
cannot be explained in terms of habit—freedom, creativity, spontaneity, and
awareness, for example—will be put outside the domain of selfhood. This leaves
us with the possibility that the human being is not exhausted by the self, that
there are other ways of living available to each of us. This possibility is a
prerequisite of the Buddhist path.
Selfhood and habit
Habit is a familiar concept, and (as for many things) its familiarity is both a
blessing and a curse. Perhaps because we all recognise the notion of habit, and
have first-hand acquaintance with at least some of its effects, most philosophers
who make use of the concept do so rather uncritically. But when we do begin to
reflect on habit, we find that neither its meaning nor its mechanism is self-evident.
In addition to its various philosophical uses, the concept of habit has several
different, although related, senses within everyday language. We know that habit
signifies ‘a settled disposition or tendency to act in a certain way, especially one
acquired by frequent repetition of the same act until it becomes almost or quite
involuntary’ (OED). Habit also denotes an individual’s outward demeanour,
posture, bodily constitution; a mode of dress; a place of dwelling. In botany, a
plant’s habit is the shape and direction of its growth; in mineralogy, a crystal’s
THEORY AND PRACTICE OF ANATTA 77
habit is its pattern of formation. These different uses of the word contribute to my
own philosophical concept of habit, which identifies three key elements: action,
repetition, and shape or form.
By action I mean mental, vocal, or physical action. Curiously, habit is at once
a source and a result of action. The phenomenon of habit testifies to the power of
action not merely to produce an effect, but to generate and to shape further
actions. Actions, when repeated, lead to the formation of a habit; a habit
represents a sort of accumulation of actions. This accumulation of repeated
actions—or of some kind of trace of these actions—gives rise to subsequent
actions, so that we can, and frequently do, ‘act out of habit’. The continuity of
habits relies on repetition: repetition sustains the habit, and the habit sustains the
repetition—habit is inseparable from repetition. Habit gives us a principle of
continuity through time that is itself temporal, since repetition is unthinkable
without time. The concept of repetition finds its philosophical significance in the
reflection—crystallised by Kierkegaard, and developed by Deleuze and Derrida—
that, because existence continually becomes, things ‘stay the same’ only if they are
repeatedly renewed, only by virtue of movement and difference. Habit is
essentially dynamic, but also essentially conservative; it has, or rather is, a self-
perpetuating force, its own momentum.
Deleuze states that, at least for an empiricist, ‘the [human] subject is
defined according to the movement through which it develops’ (1991, 85). In
the Preface to his essay on Hume, Empiricism and Subjectivity, Deleuze
highlights Hume’s concept of habit (one of his ‘most essential and creative
contributions’ to philosophy), and suggests that ‘there is no more striking
answer to the problem of the self’ than the discovery that we are ‘nothing but
habits—the habit of saying “I”’. Deleuze is suggesting that the continuity and
stability of this ‘I’ should be explained by habit, rather than by a metaphysical
concept of substance or essence, or by a doctrine of divine creation; he is
identifying habit as ‘the movement through which [the self] develops’, and thus
offering an empiricist definition of the self. In fact, Deleuze describes his own
philosophy as ‘transcendental empiricism’, and the influence of Kant and
Husserl is evident in his interpretation of Hume: ‘Habit is the constitutive root of
the subject, and the subject, at root, is the synthesis of time—the synthesis of
the present and the past in the light of the future’ (Deleuze 1991, 92–3). In
other words, subjectivity is constituted by a synthesis that ‘posits the past as a
rule for the future’ (Deleuze 1991, 92–4). I find Deleuze’s account of the self
attractive because it is naturalistic (habit is a principle of nature; we can
understand plants, animals, and people in terms of their habits); because it is at
least in part empirical (habits can be observed, and the mechanism of habit can
be scientifically modelled); and because it accommodates both physical and
psychological aspects of selfhood, and treats the living, embodied ‘I’ more
holistically than most rival accounts.
Another point in favour of this interpretation of the self is that it includes,
and emphasises, the sociality and worldliness of selfhood. We ‘catch’ habits
78 C. CARLISLE
from people who we spend a lot of time with, adopting and making our own
their manners of speech, their gestures, their ways of dressing, even their
patterns of thought and behaviour. Habit accomplishes a kind of compromise
and adaptation between beings and their environment. We might regard habit
as a fundamental mode of what Heidegger calls ‘being-in-the-world’: in this
case, the close connection between habit and habitat resonates with
Heidegger’s predilection for the vocabulary of dwelling and abiding. The
self’s capacity to be affected and shaped by actions renders it irreducibly
worldly, so that the distinction between one’s habits and one’s habitat is less
clear than we might suppose. This is particularly true of linguistic habits: in
order to communicate we must repeat words, phrases, gestures, and
intonations already in circulation, already meaningful, and this mobile resource
of signs is the habitat or ‘house of being’, which domesticates—renders familiar
and orderly—the flux of sense experience. At the same time, habit individuates
in so far as each being is a unique configuration of habits, a singular site of
repetition.
Deleuze’s claim that habit offers an account of the self leaves us with the
task of accounting for habit. (In Difference and Repetition, Deleuze (1994) goes
some way toward doing this, although here he gives less emphasis to habit.) How
are habits formed? How must a being be constituted in order to be capable of
habit? To begin with, habit presupposes a capacity to accumulate or contract
repeated actions; and a capacity to be formed by this repetition. We can
distinguish four transcendental conditions of habit, two corresponding to each of
these capacities: retention and synthesis, affectivity and plasticity. First, then, the
phenomenon of habit implies the retention and the synthesis of repeated
elements. Repetition is productive—the second time adding to the first—only if
actions can be stored, accumulated, held together; only if the past can be
contracted within the present. For Hume (as for Kant) the imagination fulfils this
function; Deleuze describes the subject’s contractile power as ‘contemplative’, a
kind of ‘passive synthesis’ that makes possible the active synthesis of memory.
Habit requires the retention of traces of past actions, but it does not require
memory; indeed, the more deeply habitual an action, the less likely we are to
remember performing it.
Second, the formative effects of habit imply the affectivity and plasticity of
the subject. As Spinoza emphasises, the nature of any individual depends on its
capacity to be affected: the complexity and sophistication of human beings is an
outcome of our sensitivity to affection in so many different ways. We are shaped
by what we suffer, and these sufferings affect us precisely in so far as we are able
to receive and retain impressions, and to be modified by them. We speak of being
‘scarred’ by traumatic experiences, but it is more important to recognise that we
are scarred or formed, in however slight a way, by our own actions (mental, vocal,
or physical). Again, we see that subjectivity is dynamic: we are continuously
forming—whether re-forming or re-affirming—our selves. It is often supposed
that people become less impressionable as they grow older, when habits harden
THEORY AND PRACTICE OF ANATTA 79
into a fixed character that is increasingly difficult to alter. William James remarks
rather wistfully that if only the young were to realise ‘how soon they will become
mere walking bundles of habits, they would give more heed to their conduct while
they are in the plastic state’ (1977, 20).
In addition to the transcendental conditions of retention, synthesis,
affectivity, and plasticity, there is a quality of inattention that seems to be
essential to habit. I regard this less as a capacity than as a function of habit.
One of the reasons why habit is so useful to us is that it saves time and
energy, promotes efficiency, and leaves our attention free to focus on other
things. Without habit we would have to concentrate very hard on every little
daily task—and we would certainly never get around to doing philosophy or
practising Buddhism. The development and success of the human species
depends on habit. William James emphasises the role of habit in this respect,
pointing out that habit ‘simplifies our movements, makes them accurate, and
diminishes fatigue [by reducing] the conscious attention with which our
actions are performed’. In fact, James claims that ‘habit depends on sensations
not attended to’ (1977, 12–14).
Repetition tends to have a numbing effect: the more we become used
to something, the less we notice and question it. For this reason we take for
granted—and assume as our own—those things that are most constant and
familiar: our bodies, our parents, our native language, the level of material
comfort with which we grow up. Of course, these are sorely missed when
they are no longer with us: habit’s inattentiveness at once creates and
obscures profound attachment, and this leads to suffering when things
change. It is this aspect of habit that most interests Proust, who describes
habit as:
an annihilating force which suppresses the originality and even the awareness of
one’s perceptions ... a dread deity, so riveted to one’s being, its insignificant face
so incrusted in one’s heart, that if it detaches itself, if it turns away from one, this
deity that one had barely distinguished inflicts on one sufferings more terrible
than any other and is then as cruel as death itself. (1996, vol. 5, 478)
The narrator of A la recherche du temps perdu endures acute discomfort on his first
night at the Grand Hotel in Balbec, finding his perceptions ‘on the permanent
footing of a vigilant defensive’ in a strange, indifferent room ‘full of things which
did not know [him]’. Unable to sleep, he is ‘tormented’ by the ticking clock, the
violet curtains, the glass-fronted bookcases. Last year, I had a similarly unpleasant
experience when I arrived in a small town in Minnesota, where I was to spend a
month working. All at once I had a new home, a new neighbourhood, a new
workplace, and new colleagues, and I felt quite alarmed: most of my habits had
abruptly become redundant, and it took continual effort to interact with and make
sense of my world. Only when new habits formed (which fortunately happens very
quickly) could I feel settled and ‘at home’ again—and after a few weeks I was
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin